58.
Innovation by interaction
In the previous item in this blog I discussed
the importance of cognitive distance for learning and innovation, in
collaboration between people or organizations. Such distance should be large
enough to tell or show each other something new but not so large that there is
no mutual understanding and tolerance. How, more precisely, does that work?
Here I apply my theory of invention (nr. 31).
In the previous item I also showed that at any
cognitive distance, people are faced with the need not only to fit their ideas
into one’s own, but also the need to help others to fit one’s own ideas and
practices into their cognition. Thus people can help each other to cross
cognitive distance and trigger shifts of thought.
In terms of the cycle of invention discussed in
item 31, this positing of one’s ideas into the minds of others entails generalization,
the attempt to apply one’s ideas into novel areas. Depending on cognitive
distance, this yields misfits in understanding that require adjustment. People
will try to ‘put it differently’, thinking back to how they came to grips with
the idea, what other ideas they tried, and what other ideas are related to it,
in their experience. In terms of the cycle of invention, this entails differentiation.
As people do this reciprocally, they are stimulated to try and fit elements of
the other’s thought into their own thinking, in hybrids of thought and practice
(reciprocation), which stimulate a novel integration of joint thinking
and action (accommodation).
One can increase abilities to cross cognitive
distance by an accumulation of knowledge and experience in the practice of
crossing distance. However, as one
accumulates knowledge one needs to search at increasing cognitive distance to
still encounter something new, finding fewer and fewer sources of further
novelty, and increasingly one has only oneself to counsel. Geniuses and wise people are lonely.
The
two-sidedness or reciprocity of the process of learning by interaction yields
immense leverage, compared to interaction with non-human nature, since in the
mutual adaptation of discourse the ‘receiver’ can shift his stance and outlook
to catch a meaning and the ‘sender’ can adapt to such stance in pitching his
meaning, and revising his metaphors and bringing in meanings from yet other
contexts.
The cycle
of invention is my answer to the old problem of object and subject, or of the
outside and the inside, as I discussed in item 23. Are objects in the world
causes of the cognition of the perceiving subject, in the form of
representations in the mind, as empiricism claims, or are objects perceived in
terms of prior cognitive categories of the subject (such as time, space and
causality), as idealism claims, or are object and subject inseparable (as
Schopenhauer claimed). According to the cycle all three are right. Objects are
perceived and made sense of in terms of categories employed by the subject but
those may be changed (in accommodation) in the process of absorbing
perceptions into mental categories (in assimilation).
No comments:
Post a Comment