164. Trust as virtue
Here I pick up elements from the earlier analysis of trust in this blog (in items 68-73).
As I
discussed there, trust is a matter not only of intentions but also of
competences. One must not only have good intentions but also the ability to act
upon them.
Trust is
emotional since it is accompanied by risk, fear, hope and doubt. It is rational
in the analysis of reasons why the trustee, the trusted person,
organization or system, may or may not be trustworthy.
Trustworthiness
requires virtues of character, such as being reasonable, forbearance,
commitment, endurance, consistency, empathy, openness, courage, and the right
amount of self-confidence.
A shortage
of self-confidence breeds suspicion, out of an excessive sense of
vulnerability. Too much self-confidence blinds one to risks or overestimates
ability to deal with them.
Trust
requires courage because it presupposes acceptance of uncertainty. If one were
certain about what will happen and what people will do, there would be no talk
of trust.
Trust
requires reasonableness, forbearance, and reciprocity, give and take, in taking
appropriate action. When something goes wrong one should not immediately
conclude foul play. One should extend benefit of the doubt and give an
opportunity to explain what happened. Disappointment of expectations may be due
to a mishap that is no one’s fault, a shortfall of competence, or lack of
attention or commitment, rather than bad intent. Then one must have endurance
and commitment to help improvements. In other words, one should not immediately
go for ‘exit’, but give ‘voice’ a chance.
Conversely,
when one makes an error, one should own up to it, explain, help to redress
damage, and show how one aims to prevent similar errors in future. One should
also be open concerning one’s fears. That gives the other side an opportunity
to take action to mitigate them. In other words: trust requires openness.
Empathy is
needed to understand the motives and position of others, including threats they
suffer, in order to take them into account in forbearance, and to judge risks
and reliability.
Trust is
not ‘being nice’. Precisely because there is trust one can afford to be
critical.
More trust
can allow for less control, but trust is not boundless and where it ends
control must start. Trust is not unconditional. In case of persistent error or
cheating, controls are tightened, or voice turns into exit.
Trust is
imperfect. It breaks under pressures of survival, as in times of crisis. Then
self-interest is likely to prevail, and relations may break. The challenge then
is to end a relationship in as trustworthy a fashion as possible, helping to
limit the damage it causes, and helping the other side in the exit.
One may also face different, conflicting obligations, to family, job, community, and conscience, and one may have to choose.
Finally,
apart from trust as a means to govern relationships, it also has intrinsic
value: for many people, for virtuous people, dealing on the basis of trust is
more agreeable and is part of humane relationships.
In sum,
trust requires virtues of courage, self-confidence, forbearance, openness,
reasonableness, endurance, and voice. One should analyze specific events in
specific conditions, with an open mind, to arrive at appropriate action. One
can encounter conflicting obligations. One should seek a balance between trust
and control, between self-interest and altruism. And trust also has intrinsic
value.
The capability of trust is a good example of what Aristotle called ‘practical reason’.
No comments:
Post a Comment