65. Otherhumanism
In item 57
I argued that there is more or less cognitive distance between people,
and that this difference yields a problem, in lack of mutual understanding, but
also an opportunity for learning. If objective knowledge is impossible then
testing our insights on what ‘others have made of it’ is the only chance we
have to correct our errors.
In item 31 I summarized a cycle of invention in which application of
existing knowledge and competence to novel contexts, with new challenges and
opportunities, can lead to new knowledge and competence. In item 58 that
insight was applied for a deeper insight into how communication, by fitting
each other’s different insights into each other’s cognitive structures can lead
to their transformation. That yields deeper insight into the importance of the
other for learning by the self.
In
language, there is Wittgenstein’s argument of the impossibility of a private
language. The self needs the other to establish meaning and for making sense.
In item 37 on the change of meaning I applied the theory of invention to change
of meaning. Universals derive their meaning from specific cases and as
abstractions from them are only temporary, forming a platform for application
in novel contexts by which universals and their meanings shift.
In item 60
I discussed Nietzsche’s (mostly implicit) assumption that the self can rise
above itself without the need for any other. In item 61 I discussed Levinas, as
a polar opposite to Nietzsche, in recognition of the need of the self to open
up to the other as a source of transcendence.
In sum, my
argument for otherhumanism is as follows. Any hereafter as life after death is
an illusion. The hereafter is not you yourself but the people and their
environment that you leave behind. If you want to make your life worthwhile and
dedicate yourself to the hereafter then the only way is dedication to others
and to the society of the future. Dedication to others is not at the expense of
yourself and life. The self needs others to escape from illusory certainties as
well as doubt, to achieve the highest possible level of freedom, to achieve its
potential, to develop and transcend itself, and thereby to utilize the unique
gift of life.
This leads
to a notion of the flourishing of life that goes beyond the life of the self,
not in a claim to any absolute, universal good beyond the world, but in
participation and contribution to the flourishing of others, during and after
our life.
The views and analyses that I present in
this blog are perhaps more congenial with Eastern, in particular Chinese,
philosophy than with Western philosophy. Later, in a sequel to the present
blog, I will consider that in some detail. For the moment, let me just give a
few indications. My otherhumanism seems close to the social
humanism of Confucius, with its perspective of
benevolence (although I do not much like the importance assigned to propriety,
ritual and respect for authority). In Buddhism and in Chinese philosophy I find
interest in change and impermanence, in different ways, which is congenial to
my imperfection on the move. The Chinese notions of yin and yang, and later developments
in neo-Confucianism (e.g. in the notions of opening and closing in the
philosophy of Xiang Shili) seem to have some resemblance to my cycle of invention.
There is a strong tradition of integrating thought and action, which is
congenial to the pragmatism that I preach and practice.
No comments:
Post a Comment