Friday, January 10, 2020


457. Issues for change in economics



The criticism of dominant, orthodox economics, and demands for its change, have intensified since the financial crisis in 2008. Sources of those protests are heterodox economics, such as post-Keynesian economics, evolutionary economics, (new) institutional economics. and social economics, and the international movement of young economists with the name ‘Rethinking economics’.



Some of the criticism and proposals for change were given in previous items of this blog, collected in a bundle posted on economics on my website bartnooteboom.nl. They were also elaborated in a recent book[i]. Here I review the criticism and make additions. The order is arbitrary, does not signify priority.



1.      The issue of uncertainty. Keynes was one the few economists to take it seriously and see its consequences. Under uncertainty one cannot calculate, and calculative rationality is a cornerstone of orthodox economics. The results are bandwagon effects and hypes, as Keynes recognized.

2.      The issue of maximizing a utility function. People are not only limitedly rational (see below), but things of value cannot all be subsumed under a single utility.  That applies to work, as a source of income and a source of satisfaction, in giving pleasure or a sense of accomplishment, and social recognition. It applies, in particular, to moral values that one does not always practise for their utility, but because they constitute what one feels one should practise, and that is who one wants to be.  That can apply also to trust, which can be useful, as a ‘lubricant for relations’ but also has intrinsic value. Another problem of utility is that it is purely conceptual, and cannot be observed directly. Utility maximization is unfalsifiable: one can always conceive of some utility function whose maximization reproduces observed behaviour. That unfalsifiability makes it scientifically dubious.

3.      The  ‘preferences’ that underlie choice are partly formed, or adjusted, in the process of choosing and acting upon them.

4.      Due to the role of subconscious processes of choice, as taught in social psychology, people are limitedly rational: do not always make rational choices. That can be very effective, in routine conduct, but it does not satisfy the assumption, in economics,  of rational choice.          

5.      Transaction costs, such as caused by imperfect information, cause ‘market failures’, of misjudging quality and reliability, the incompleteness and cost of collecting information, making contracts or other agreements and controlling their execution.

6.      The condition that relations require ‘specific investments’ that have value only, or mostly, in that relationship, which make one dependent, and create a need for the relationship to last some minimum time, to recoup that investment. This pleads for ‘optimal’, not maximum flexibility.

7.      The human need for local roots, which obstruct the economic credo of maximum mobility of resources, including labour, which in globalisation erode local communities and work relations, and sources of respect and reputation.

8.      The self is not autonomous, as assumed in economics. One does not only need the other for the advantage of division of labour, but one is constituted  in action in the world, in interaction with others. Opposition by others yields the highest form of freedom: freedom from prejudice.

9.      The need for trust, for agreeable relations and the economy. Some economists claim that trust cannot survive in markets, due to competition, but competition is not always so strong as to prevent some slack for sacrifices for trust, and, more fundamentally, in so far as survival requires innovation, that brings uncertainty, which requires the ‘leap of trust’, and therefore I turn it around: in markets one needs trust.

10.  In so far as economists take into account issues of information and knowledge, they take it for granted, tacitly most of the time, that in relations there should minimum of ‘cognitive distance’, difference in ideas. But such difference also has value, as source of innovation. Rather than minimum difference there should therefore be ‘optimal distance’, in a trade-off between distance as an obstacle for understanding and as a source of difference for innovation.



Most of these points entail a ‘paradigm shift’, and one can ask if this is still economics. That is probably why they tend to be ignored or neglected by economists.     



[i] Bart Nooteboom, Uprooting economics; a manifesto for change, Edward Elgar, 2019.

No comments:

Post a Comment