Sunday, August 21, 2016


277. In search of a supergame

In foregoing items in this blog I used the notion of a ‘language game’. How are such games related to each other? I talked of ‘stepping from a language game into a wider one’. Baseball and soccer are games in wider class of ball games. This suggests a hierarchy of games, which may suggest some game ‘at the top’, which all games obey. I do think there are nested games, but I do not think there is a hierarchy of all games, governed by some supergame at the top.

Some crucial language games are those concerning justice and ethics. They are rivals. One, the dominant one in western societies, is liberal individualism, with its utility ethics, looking only at outcomes of actions, effected in markets. An older one is Aristotelian virtue ethics and corresponding practical wisdom, aimed at a notion of ‘the good life’ in the social context of a specific community (‘polis’). Another is theological, based on some moral sense granted by God (Augustine, Hutcheson). Yet another one is based on rationally adopted duties that apply universally, regardless of interests (Kant).

Can these rival views be reconciled, compared or judged from the perspective of some wider, encompassing language game? Or are there, at best, some family resemblances?

In this blog I have adopted the notion of ‘warranted assertibility’, rather than ‘truth’, and the warrant depends on the perspective. I have employed a pragmatic perspective by which ideas and actions are evaluated on the basis of the extent that they ‘work’, logically, empirically, and practically. Does this offer the basis for evaluating rival views of justice and ethics? Those will generally share a respect for some form of logic. Empirical performance depends on facts, but those are interpretations based on conceptualizations connected to the perspective one holds. Practical performance in action depends on evaluation criteria that are also part of the adopted perspective: producing utility, conducive to the good life, obedience to God.

So, while they do share elements, in some family resemblance, they differ on fundamental points. In contrast with all others, liberalism is not oriented towards any notion of the good life. It claims to be neutral with regard to morality and goodness, leaving those up to individuals to choose for themselves. Citizens have preferences from whatever conception of the good life that they may have, and markets serve to allow them to pursue those preferences. So, goodness is not only lacking as a guide, it is ruled out of consideration.

Theological and Aristotelian perspectives differ fundamentally in adopting or not faith in a providential God. In Aristotelian ethics practical reason guides action, while according to David Hume ‘reason is the slave of the passions’.

If there is no overarching supergame, is there still any way in which rival views can rationally criticize each other, or are they irredeemably ‘incommensurable’?

Alasdair MacIntyre develops the following argument.[i]  First of all it is important to realize that perspectives of justice are historical, as traditions that form and change in specific social settings and cultures. While in a static view differences between perspectives are irreconcilable, without any ‘master game’ to adjudicate between them, in a dynamic view of how they develop there may be a way for them to learn from each other.

Traditions adapt in time as experience accrues and conditions change, though they maintain some ‘core’ of fundamental principles. Can they also mutate into some hybrid, some body of ‘novel combinations’, by some dialectical process of conflicts and their resolution? That would require some beginnings of a common language.

One may try to understand a rival perspective and then look critically from that perspective at comparative performance. Does the rival succeed where one’s own view fails, perhaps? This requires tolerance for ambiguity, paradox and discrepancies of meaning, trying out things even if they seem nonsensical in one’s own view. From a pragmatic perspective such attempt would require immersion in the foreign culture, in its practices and its language, preferably in the form of a common project with the ‘natives’. Mutual dependence in trying to succeed with the project provides an incentive for sharing. Sharing successes and failures one may gather insight in the relative merits of the different perspectives.

This fits well with the dialectical ‘cycle of discovery’ that I presented in this blog (items 31, 138). There, the basic logic is as follows. Try to implement your existing view in a novel, foreign context, to discover where it fails while a local practice succeeds. Next, make hybrids from elements from one’s own and from the other’s context and experiment with them. This mixing of apparent incommensurables will yield anomalies of meanings that do not fit together. Nevertheless the hybrid yields a basis for exploring the potential of novel elements. That may lead to an ‘accommodation’ to a novel, more coherent synthesis. But the outcome is not a universal, fixed supergame, and will itself be replaced in due course. A paralympic game, you might say. Imperfection on the move.

Could such a procedure perhaps lead to a novel synthesis of, say, liberal and Aristotelian justice and ethics? That is what I have tried to do in a proposal for radical change in economic theory.[ii]      


[i] Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose justice? Whose rationality?, University of Notre Dame Press, 1988.
[ii] Bart Nooteboom, How markets work and fail, and what to make of them, Edward Elgar, 2014, paperback 2015.

No comments:

Post a Comment